《Human Rights.doc》由会员分享,可在线阅读,更多相关《Human Rights.doc(13页珍藏版)》请在三一办公上搜索。
1、Human RightsJames W. Nickel Jim Nickel has published widely in philosophy and law journals. He joined the faculty at ASU College of Law in 2003 after 21 years as Professor of Philosophy at theUniversity of Colorado, Boulder. Nickel has been a visiting professor at the UC Berkeley School of Law (Boal
2、t Hall) and at the University of Utah. At the University of Colorado Nickel served as Director of the Center for Values and Social Policy from 1982-88 and as Chair of the Philosophy Department from 1992-1996. Nickel has received many fellowships including a National Endowment for the Humanities Fell
3、owship, a Rockefeller Foundation Humanities Fellowship, an ACLS Fellowship, and a National Humanities Center Fellowship. In fall 2004 he was a Visiting Fellow at Corpus Christi College, Oxford University. Nickel was recently awarded the Philosophical Quarterlys 2004 essay prize for his paper, Povert
4、y and Rights.Introduction:Human rights are international moral and legal norms that aspire to protect all people everywhere from severe political, legal, and social abuses. Examples of human rights are the right to freedom of religion, the right to a fair trial when charged with a crime, the right n
5、ot to be tortured, and the right to engage in political activity. These rights exist in morality and in law at the national and international levels. They are addressed primarily to governments, requiring compliance and enforcement. The main source of the contemporary conception of human rights is t
6、he Universal Declaration of Human Rights (United Nations, 1948b) and the many human rights documents and treaties that have followed in its wake. 1The General Idea of Human RightsThe Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR; United Nations 1948b) sets out a list of over two dozen specific human r
7、ights that countries should respect and protect. We may group these specific rights into six or more families: security rights that protect people against crimes such as murder, massacre, torture, and rape; liberty rights that protect freedoms in areas such as belief, expression, association, assemb
8、ly, and movement; political rights that protect the liberty to participate in politics through actions such as communicating, assembling, protesting, voting, and serving in public office; due process rights that protect against abuses of the legal system such as imprisonment without trial, secret tr
9、ials, and excessive punishments; equality rights that guarantee equal citizenship, equality before the law, and nondiscrimination; and welfare rights (or economic and social rights) that require provision of education to all children and protections against severe poverty and starvation. Another fam
10、ily that might be included is group rights. The UDHR does not include group rights, but subsequent treaties do. Group rights include protections of ethnic groups against genocide and the ownership by countries of their national territories and resources. The general idea of human rights can be expla
11、ined by setting out some defining features. It answers the question of what human rights are with a general description of the concept rather than a list of specific rights. Two people can have the same general idea of human rights even though they disagree about whether some particular rights are h
12、uman rights.Human rights are political norms dealing mainly with how people should be treated by their governments and institutions. They are not ordinary moral norms applying mainly to interpersonal conduct (such as prohibitions of lying and violence). As Thomas Pogge puts it, to engage human right
13、s, conduct must be in some sense official . But we must be careful here since some rights, such as rights against racial and sexual discrimination are primarily concerned to regulate private behavior. Still, governments are directed in two ways by rights against discrimination. They forbid governmen
14、ts to discriminate in their actions and policies, and they impose duties on governments to prohibit and discourage both private and public forms of discrimination.Second, human rights exist as moral and/or legal rights. A human right can exist as a shared norm of actual human moralities, as a justif
15、ied moral norm supported by strong reasons, as a legal right at the national level (here it might be referred to as a civil or constitutional right), or as a legal right within international law. The aspiration of the human rights movement is that all human rights will come to exist in all four ways
16、. Third, human rights are numerous (several dozen) rather than few. John Lockes rights to life, liberty, and property were few and abstract, but human rights as we know them today address specific problems (e.g., guaranteeing fair trials, ending slavery, ensuring the availability of education, preve
17、nting genocide.) They protect people against familiar abuses of fundamental human interests. Because many concern contemporary institutions and problems they are not transhistorical. One could formulate human rights abstractly or conditionally to make them transhistorical, but the fact remains that
18、the formulations in contemporary human rights documents are neither abstract nor conditional. They presuppose criminal trials, governments funded by income taxes, and formal systems of education.Fourth, human rights are minimal standards. They are concerned with avoiding the terrible rather than wit
19、h achieving the best. Their focus is protecting minimally good lives for all people. Henry Shue suggests that human rights concern the lower limits on tolerable human conduct rather than great aspirations and exalted ideals. As minimal standards they leave most legal and policy matters open to democ
20、ratic decision-making at the national and local levels. This allows them to accommodate a great deal of cultural and institutional variation.Fifth, human rights are international norms covering all countries and all people living today. They are the sorts of norms that are appropriately recommended
21、to all countries. International law plays a crucial role in giving human rights global reach. We can say that human rights are universal provided that we recognize that some rights, such as the right to vote, are held only by adult citizens; that some human rights documents focus on vulnerable group
22、s such as children, women, and indigenous peoples; and that some rights, such as the right against genocide, are group rights.Sixth, human rights are high-priority norms. As Maurice Cranston put it Atest of a human rightis the test of paramount importance. A human right is something of which no one
23、may be deprived without a grave affront to justice. This does not mean, however, that we should take human rights to be absolute. As James Griffin says, human rights should be understood as resistant to trade-offs, but not too resistant. The high priority of human rights needs support from a plausib
24、le connection with fundamental human interests or powerful normative considerations.Seventh, human rights have robust justifications that apply everywhere and support their high priority. Without this they cannot withstand cultural diversity and national sovereignty. Robust justifications are powerf
25、ul but need not be understood as ones that are irresistible.Eighth, human rights are rights, but not necessarily in a strict sense. As rights they have several features. One is that they have rightholders - a person or agency having a particular right. Broadly, the rightholders of human rights are a
26、ll people living today. More precisely, they are sometimes all people, sometimes all citizens of countries, sometimes all members of groups with particular vulnerabilities (women, children, racial and religious minorities, indigenous peoples), and sometimes all ethnic groups (as with rights against
27、genocide.) Another feature of rights is that they focus on a freedom, protection, status, or benefit. A right is always to something which is the focus of the rightholders interest. Rights also have addressees who are assigned duties or responsibilities. A persons human rights are not primarily righ
28、ts against the United Nations or other international bodies; they primarily impose obligations on the government of the country in which the person resides or is located. The human rights of a citizen of Belgium are mainly addressed to his government. International agencies, and the governments of c
29、ountries other than ones own, are secondary or backup addressees. International human rights organizations provide encouragement, assistance, and sometimes criticism to states in order to assist them in fulfilling their duties. The duties associated with human rights typically require actions involv
30、ing respect, protection, facilitation, and provision. Finally, rights are usually mandatory in the sense of imposing duties on their addressees, but they sometimes do little more than declare high-priority goals and assign responsibility for their progressive realization. For example, the Internatio
31、nal Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, which covers rights to basic human needs such as food, clothing, housing, and education, commits its signatories to take steps.to the maximum of.available resources, with a view to achieving progressively the full realization of the rights recog
32、nized in the present Covenant. It is possible to argue, of course, that goal-like rights are not real rights, but it may be better to recognize that they compromise a weaker or looser notion of a right.Having set out a general idea of human rights with eight elements, it is useful to consider three
33、other candidates which I think should be rejected. The first is the claim that all human rights are negative rights, in the sense that they only require governments to refrain from doing things. On this view, human rights never require governments to take positive steps such as protecting and provid
34、ing. This claim is not compatible with the attractive view that one of the main jobs of governments is to protect peoples rights by creating a system of criminal law and of legal property rights. The European Convention on Human Rights incorporates this view when it says that Everyones right to life
35、 shall be protected by law (Article 2.1). And the UN Torture Convention (United Nations 1984) imposes the requirement that Each State Party shall ensure that all acts of torture are offences under its criminal law (Article 4.1).A second claim to be rejected is that human rights are inalienable. Inal
36、ienability does not mean that rights are absolute or can never be overridden by other considerations. To say that a right is inalienable means that its holder cannot lose it temporarily or permanently by bad conduct or by voluntarily giving it up. I doubt that all human rights are inalienable in thi
37、s sense. If we believe in imprisonment for legal crimes, then peoples rights to freedom of movement can be forfeited temporarily or permanently by just convictions of serious crimes. And the right to freedom of movement can be voluntarily alienated by a person who makes a lifelong commitment to live
38、 in a monastery. Human rights are not inalienable but they are hard to lose.Third, I think we should reject John Rawls proposal in The Law of Peoples that by definition human rights define where legitimate toleration of other countries ends. Rawls says that human rights specify limits to a regimes i
39、nternal autonomy and that their fulfillment is sufficient to exclude justified and forceful intervention by other peoples, for example, by diplomatic and economic sanctions, or in grave cases by military force.It is a grave oversimplification to suggest that there is a line defined by human rights w
40、here national sovereignty ends. There is no need to deny that human rights are helpful in identifying the limits of justifiable toleration, but there are several reasons to doubt that they simply define that boundary. First, the fulfillment of human rights is a very vague idea. No country fully sati
41、sfies human rights; all countries have significant human rights problems. Some countries have large human rights problems, and many have massive problems (gross violations of human rights). Beyond this, the responsibility of the current government of a country for these problems also varies. The mai
42、n responsibility may belong to the previous government and the current government may be taking reasonable steps to move towards greater compliance.Further, defining human rights as norms that set the bounds of toleration requires restricting human rights to only a few fundamental rights. Rawls sugg
43、ests the following list: the right to life (to the means of subsistence and security); to liberty (to freedom from slavery, serfdom, and forced occupation, and to a sufficient measure of liberty of conscience to ensure freedom of religion and thought); to property (personal property); and to formal
44、equality as pressed by the rules of natural justice (that is, that similar cases be treated similarly). As Rawls recognizes this list leaves out most freedoms, rights of political participation, equality rights, and welfare rights. Leaving out any protection for equality and democracy is a high pric
45、e to pay for assigning human rights the role of setting the bounds of tolerance, and we can accommodate Rawls underlying idea without paying it. The underlying idea is that countries with massive violations of the most important human rights are not to be tolerated - particularly when the notion of
46、toleration implies, as Rawls thinks it does, full and equal membership in good standing in the community of nations. But to use this idea we do not need to follow Rawls in equating human rights with some radically stripped down list of human rights. Instead we can develop a doctrine - which is neede
47、d for other purposes anyway - of which human rights are the most important. Massive violations of the most fundamental rights can then be used as grounds for non-tolerance.2. The Existence of Human RightsThe most obvious way in which human rights exist is as norms of national and international law c
48、reated by enactment and judicial decisions. At the international level, human rights norms exist because of treaties that have turned them into international law. For example, the human right not to be held in slavery or servitude in Article 4 of ECHR and in Article 8 of ICCPR exists because these t
49、reaties enact it at the international level. At the national level, human rights norms exist because they have through enactment, judicial decision, or custom become part of a countrys law. For example, the right against slavery exists in the United States because the Thirteenth Amendment to the US Constitution prohibits slavery and servitude. When rights are embedded in international law we speak of them as human rights; but when they are enacted in national law we more frequ
链接地址:https://www.31ppt.com/p-3023180.html