Forms of knowledge in mathematics and mathematics education Philosophical and rhetorical perspectives.doc
《Forms of knowledge in mathematics and mathematics education Philosophical and rhetorical perspectives.doc》由会员分享,可在线阅读,更多相关《Forms of knowledge in mathematics and mathematics education Philosophical and rhetorical perspectives.doc(17页珍藏版)》请在三一办公上搜索。
1、FORMS OF KNOWLEDGE IN MATHEMATICS AND MATHEMATICS EDUCATION: PHILOSOPHICAL AND RHETORICAL PERSPECTIVESPaul ErnestExeter University, UK, Oslo University, Norway, Brunel University, UKp.ernest(at)ex.ac.ukABSTRACTNew forms of mathematical knowledge are growing in importance for mathematics and educatio
2、n, including tacit knowledge; knowledge of particulars, language and rhetoric in mathematics. These developments also include a recognition of the philosophical import of the social context of mathematics, and are part of the diminished domination of the field by absolutist philosophies. From an epi
3、stemological perspective, all knowledge must have a warrant and it is argued in the paper that tacit knowledge is validated by public performance and demonstration. This enables a parallel to be drawn between the justification of knowledge, and the assessment of learning. An important factor in the
4、warranting of knowledge is the means of communicating it convincingly in written form, i.e., the rhetoric of mathematics. Skemps concept of logical understanding anticipates the significance of tacit rhetorical knowledge in school mathematics. School mathematics has a range of rhetorical styles, and
5、 when one is used appropriately it indicates to the teacher the level of a students understanding. The paper highlights the import of attending to rhetoric and the range of rhetorical styles in school mathematics, and the need for explicit instruction in the area.BACKGROUND In the past decade or two
6、, there have been a number of developments in the history, and philosophy and social studies of mathematics and science which have evoked or paralleled developments in mathematics (and science) education. I shall briefly mention three of these that have significance for the main theme of this paper,
7、 the import of rhetoric and justification in mathematics and mathematics education. Even though all of the developments I mention below are continuing sites of controversy, I merely list them rather than offer extended arguments in support of the associated claims, since this would draw me away from
8、 the main theme. Anyway such arguments can be found elsewhere (e.g., Ernest 1997).An important background development has been the emergence of fallibilist perspectives in the philosophy of mathematics. These views assert that the status of mathematical truth is determined, to some extent, relative
9、to its contexts and is dependent, at least in part, on historical contingency. Thus a growing number of scholars to question the universality, absoluteness and perfectibility of mathematics and mathematical knowledge (Davis and Hersh 1980, Lakatos 1976, Tymoczko 1986, Kitcher 1984, Ernest 1997). Thi
10、s is still controversial in mathematical and philosophical circles, although less so in education and in the social and human sciences. One consequence of this perspective is a re-examination of the role and purpose of proof in mathematics. Clearly proofs serve to warrant mathematical claims and the
11、orems, but from a fallibilist perspective this warranting can no longer be taken as the provision of objective and ironclad demonstrations of absolute truth or logical validity. Mathematical proofs may be said to fulfil a variety of functions, including showing the links between different parts of k
12、nowledge (pedagogical), helping working mathematicians develop and extend knowledge (methodological), demonstrating the existence of mathematical objects (ontological), and persuading mathematicians of the validity of knowledge claims (epistemological), see, e.g., Hersh (1993) and Lakatos (1976). Be
13、low I elaborate further on the persuasive, epistemological role of proofs in mathematics.The impact of these developments on education are indirect, as they do not lead to immediate logical implications for the teaching and learning of mathematics or the mathematics curriculum without the addition o
14、f further deep assumptions (Ernest 1995). Nevertheless fallibilist philosophies of mathematics are central to a variety of theories of learning mathematics including radical constructivism (Glasersfeld 1995), social constructivism (Ernest 1991), and socio-cultural views (Lerman 1994) which can have
15、classroom consequences. The second development is the emerging view that the social context and professional communities of mathematicians play a central role in the creation and justification of mathematical knowledge (Davis and Hersh 1980, Kitcher 1984, Latour 1987). These communities are not mere
16、ly accidental or contingent collections or organisations of persons incidental to mathematics. Rather they play an essential role in epistemology in two ways: their social organisation and structure is central to the mechanisms of mathematical knowledge generation and justification, and they are the
17、 repositories and sites of application and transmission of tacit and implicit knowledge (Ernest 1997, Lave and Wenger 1991, Restivo 1992). In education, the vital roles played by the social and cultural contexts (Bauersfeld 1992, Cobb 1986, 1989), and the centrality of tacit and implicit knowledge i
18、n the mathematics classroom do not need to be argued, as they are already widely recognised (Bishop 1988, Hiebert 1986, Saxe 1991, Tirosh 1994).Third, there is a move in the sociology and philosophy of science mathematics to focus on communicative acts and performances of scientists and mathematicia
19、ns, and in particular on their rhetorical practices (Woolgar 1988, Simons 1989, Fuller 1993, Kitcher 1991). In mathematics the parallel concern has been with writing genres and proof practices (Ernest 1997, Livingston 1986, Rotman 1993). While there has been attention to the role of language in math
20、ematics education for some time (Aiken 1972, Austin and Howson 1979, Durkin and Shire 1991, Pimm 1987, Skemp 1982) it is only recently that an awareness of the significance of genres and rhetoric for the field are emerging (Ernest 1993, Morgan 1998, Mousley and Marks 1991).These background developme
21、nts raise a number of issues concerning the form or forms of mathematical knowledge and the role and function of mathematical texts and proofs within the discipline itself and in the teaching and learning of mathematics. Whereas traditionally mathematical knowledge was understood as a collection of
22、validated propositions, i.e., a set of theorems with proofs, a number of philosophers such as Ryle (1949) Polanyi (1959) Kuhn (1970) and Kitcher (1984) have argued that not all knowledge can be made explicit. The claim that know how and tacit knowledge are important in all areas of human thought inc
23、luding mathematics. The argument for including tacit know how as well as propositional knowledge as part of mathematical knowledge is that it takes human understanding, activity and experience to make or justify mathematics. Much that is accepted as a sign that persons are in possession of mathemati
24、cal knowledge consists in their being able to carry out symbolic procedures or conceptual operations. To know the addition algorithm, proof by induction or definite integrals is to be able to carry out the operations involved, not merely to be able to state certain propositions. Thus what an individ
- 配套讲稿:
如PPT文件的首页显示word图标,表示该PPT已包含配套word讲稿。双击word图标可打开word文档。
- 特殊限制:
部分文档作品中含有的国旗、国徽等图片,仅作为作品整体效果示例展示,禁止商用。设计者仅对作品中独创性部分享有著作权。
- 关 键 词:
- Forms of knowledge in mathematics and education Philosophical rhetorical perspectives

链接地址:https://www.31ppt.com/p-3022931.html